Pornography And Objectification.pdf

(110 KB) Pobierz
<!DOCTYPE html PUBLIC "-//W3C//DTD HTML 4.01//EN" "http://www.w3.org/TR/html4/strict.dtd">
PORNOGRAPHY AND OBJECTIFICATION
Re-reading “the picture that divided Britain”
Feona Attwood
Feminism, Objectification, and Pornography
In this article, I want to examine the significance of the terms “objectification” and
“pornography” and to ask how useful these are for analyses of contemporary sexual
representations. I will begin by tracing some key approaches to objectification and
pornography and by highlighting some of the differences in these approaches. While
theoretical work from a range of fields—media and cultural studies, linguistics, queer
theory and so on—has been productive in the analysis of sexual representation, it is work
which focuses most explicitly on the realm of the pornographic or on the “effect” of
sexually explicit material which has been most visible in this area of study, and which
comprises an identifiable set of key approaches. Most visible among these have been a
feminist anti-pornography position organized around the claim that sexually explicit
representation is a form of sexual violence that depends on the objectification of women
for its charge; an historical approach, which examines the regulatory significance of
pornography for modern cultures; and an attempt to pinpoint the characteristic aesthetic
features of pornography in a way that relates the pornographic to other forms of cultural
production, most particularly in terms of its transgression of dominant cultural norms. In
turn, while these general approaches have been drawn on by a variety of theorists
working within this area, they are most closely associated with particular writers, and it
is to the work of these writers that I will refer. In particular, the feminist anti-pornography
work of Andrea Dworkin ([1979] 1999), the historical account of pornographic regulation
given by Walter Kendrick ([1987] 1996), and the discussion of pornography’s transgres-
siveness put forward by Laura Kipnis (1996) will be the major points of reference.
I will argue that while all three accounts offer productive ways of framing the
analysis of sexual representations, a tendency towards essentialism in all of them serves
to limit their application. The prominence of these approaches, with their privileging of
the key terms “pornography” and “objectification,” is highly problematic for the develop-
ment of work in this area. I will attempt to demonstrate the strengths and limitations of
these approaches by focusing on the public controversy around an advert for Opium
perfume in 2000, and I will argue that a greater attentiveness to the context of particular
images and to the reactions they provoke, an attentiveness which has perhaps been more
successfully developed elsewhere in cultural studies, may provide a more helpful way of
developing the analysis of contemporary sexual representations.
The term “objectification” has been central to feminist critiques of sexual represen-
tation that examine how woman functions as a sign for patriarchy as its other, its
spectacle and its subordinate thing .Ithas also been important in establishing feminist
Feminist Media Studies Vol. 4, No. 1, 2004
ISSN 1468-0777 print/ISSN 1471-5902 online/04/010007-13
2004 Taylor & Francis Ltd DOI: 10.1080/14680770410001674617
854329544.001.png
8
FEONA ATTWOOD
critiques of pornography which focus not on “the sexual explicitness in pornography,” but
on pornography’s “sexism,” its “characteristic reduction of women to passive, perpetually
desiring bodies—or bits of bodies—eternally available for servicing men” (Lynne Segal
1992, p. 2). That pornography reduces “woman” to “object,” and that, in addition,
objectification is a form of violence against women, is made particularly explicit in the
well-known claims that, “The word pornography… means the graphic depiction of
women as vile whores …Whores exist only within a framework of male sexual domi-
nation” (Dworkin [1979] 1999, p. 200), and that, “Pornography is the theory, and rape the
practice” (Robin Morgan 1980, p. 139).
These claims, which work to link pornography, objectification, and violence so
closely, exist within a fairly wide range of feminist accounts of pornography. However,
their prominence has generally served to mask the variety of feminist discourse on sexual
representation; indeed, they have frequently been perceived as representative of feminist
views on sexuality per se . The idea that the objectification of women in pornography
works to effect sexual violence in society, is a form of sexual violence against women, and
typically involves the depiction of violence—“women … tied up, stretched, hanged,
fucked, gang-banged, whipped, beaten and begging for more” (Dworkin [1979] 1999,
p. 201)—has become well-established as a commonsense understanding of what por-
nography is, largely through repetition rather than verification. It has been particularly
influential in academic, institutional, and public understandings of sexual representation,
working to frame and structure most discussions about this type of representation since
the 1980s. For example, ongoing legal and ethical debates about emerging forms of
pornography on the Internet are still quite strongly influenced by this view, while most
analytical accounts of sexual representation take it as the starting point for discussion, the
point that enables a clear position to be taken and elaborated. Despite its inability to
define “objectification” or “pornography” very clearly, or to substantiate the impact and
significance of sexual representation, the feminist anti-pornography approach remains
important for the way it highlights the need to investigate imagery which constructs sex
and gender in ways that may be hostile to women. However, its tendency to close down
other ways of making sense of sexual representation remains deeply problematic.
Re-reading Pornography and Objectification
The real existence of any thing ought to be thrown in doubt by the failure of several
generations’ efforts to define it. (Kendrick [1987] 1996, p. xiii)
The difficulty of defining either objectification or pornography has led to two
important developments in research on pornography. The first is an historical examin-
ation of the ways in which “pornography” functions as a regulatory category that is
underpinned by particular social concerns. Walter Kendrick argues that the struggle over
pornographic definition masks a struggle over “power …access to the world around
us… control over our own bodies and our own minds” (Kendrick [1987] 1996, p. 236).
Middle-class white men have generally exercised this power over more powerless
groups—women, children, the working classes—and the creation of a “Secret Museum”
of pornographic texts has been justified in terms of a concern with the harmful effects of
these texts on such groups. This concern with pornography’s “effects” reveals a deep-
9
PORNOGRAPHY AND OBJECTIFICATION
rooted fear about the power of representation, not to mention a fear of those who are
imagined to be susceptible to this power. According to Kendrick, it is the processes of
definition, classification, and concealment that create “pornography,” and it is these
processes that are of interest to the historian. It is therefore the “perennial little
melodrama” played out around pornography (Kendrick [1987] 1996, p. xiii), in which
pornographic things function as “a symbol for anarchy” (Kendrick [1987] 1996, p.219),
and their concealment works “to regulate the behaviour of those who seem to threaten
the social order” (Kendrick [1987] 1996, p. 235), which becomes the focus of investigation
in this approach.
A second development in research on pornography involves the textual re-examin-
ation of the aesthetic, generic, and cultural characteristics of pornographic things .As
Linda Williams (1989, p.29) argues, “how can we adequately discuss the pornograph ic
without making some stab at a description of specific pornogra phy ?” While at odds with
Kendrick’s approach in its focus—Kendrick is profoundly uninterested in the “things”
which are labelled as pornography—this line of inquiry has covered some of the same
ground. The work of Laura Kipnis (1996, p.166) in particular has put forward the
argument that the pornographic genre is “a realm of transgression that is, in effect, a
counter-aesthetics to dominant norms for bodies, sexualities, and desire itself.” While it is
the struggle over pornographic definition that is crucial for Kendrick’s argument, it is the
characteristics of transgression which are of greater significance for Kipnis. Nonetheless,
both accounts produce a model in which pornographic definition is key to understanding
regulation as a power struggle over forms of representation and consumption and
between dominant norms and transgression.
These developments in the study of pornography have enabled a reconsideration
of pornography as a cultural and social category. They suggest that the regulation of
pornography involves the regulation of any representation which contradicts dominant
norms of sexuality, and an exercise of power over the lower classes, women, and children.
However, neither of these developments directly addresses the question of women’s
objectification in pornography and other representations of sexuality, and in this sense,
they are limited for the understanding of this issue which has been of such overwhelming
importance for feminist discussions of sexual politics.
As Segal (1992, p. 11) has argued, sexual politics and pornography have been
conflated in contemporary Western cultures, while political disputes over sexual power,
knowledge, and representation have often taken the form of “debates over pornography.”
The centrality of sexuality for feminist theory and activism during the 1980s tended
towards a privileging of pornography as “ the feminist issue of the 1980s” (Segal 1992,
p.3), as emblematic of women’s oppression under patriarchy at a moment when sexual
abuse, harassment, and violence appeared as the most urgent political issues for many
Western second-wave feminists. A concern with the power of images, already established
in contemporary Western cultures and newly significant in the feminist cultural politics of
the 1980s, has also underscored pornography’s apparent importance for an understand-
ing of the connections between representation and reality. Pornography has become
“overburdened with significance” (Segal 1992, p.65), as a culturally established way for
speaking about sex, power, and regulation, as a kind of shorthand for women’s discon-
tents, as an emblem of misogyny and as a symbol of the power of the image.
It is partly for these reasons that the anti-pornography feminist position still retains
its power for many feminists, and indeed for many women who do not otherwise
10
FEONA ATTWOOD
associate themselves with feminism. For them, developments within the pornography
debate may not provide a satisfactory or persuasive resolution to the claim that pornogra-
phy harms and humiliates women, either by providing a template for male sexual
behaviour, or as a representative cultural statement of woman’s purpose as a ‘thing’ for
men. As Laura Kipnis (1996, p.199) writes, for many women, this account may feel
“fundamentally irrational, but at the same time, correct.”
While there are clear historical reasons for the continuing importance of the term
“objectification” for feminist analysis—which make the shortcomings of historical and
textual accounts of pornography all the more frustrating—there are further problems
with all of the approaches I have described. These hinge on the question of how
pornography is defined in each account. While historical and textual approaches use the
term pornography quite precisely to describe texts which are produced as transgressive
through processes of regulation and restriction, or those which are restricted and
regulated because of their perceived transgressive characteristics, the claim that por-
nography objectifies women does not make use of the term in the same way, and it does
not put it to work to explore the historical and textual significance of pornography as a
category. Whereas pornography means “the representation of transgressive forms of
sexuality” for Kipnis, and “the processes used to regulate forms of sexual representation”
for Kendrick, it means “the depiction of women as sexual objects” in the anti-pornography
feminist position.
The very different starting points of writers such as Dworkin, Kendrick, and Kipnis,
and the different ways in which they use the term pornography, should, in theory, be a
productive difference which enables a multi-dimensional analysis of sexual texts and their
significance, but in practice it has tended to produce a rather difficult area of study where
the analysis of pornography and the analysis of the representation of women’s sexuality
has become somewhat unclear and entangled. It is perhaps the tendency towards
essentialism in all three accounts which has limited the development of this area of study.
While the work produced by these writers is often rich and detailed, the conclusions
which are drawn are rigid and circular. For Dworkin, all pornography objectifies women
and everything that objectifies women is pornography. According to Kendrick, all sexual
representations which are subject to regulation become pornography, and all attempts to
regulate pornography are an exercise of power over powerless groups, including women.
For Kipnis, pornography always transgresses dominant norms of sexuality and gender,
and whatever is sexual and transgressive is pornography. Little attention is given to the
range of texts or practices, which may constitute the representation of sexuality at any
given point, or to the contexts in which sexual representations are produced, circulated,
consumed, debated, or regulated. Because of this, the positions taken by these theorists
appear to cancel each other out in terms of their usefulness for discussing the political
significance of sexual representations, and they are limited in terms of their application
to a wide range of examples.
Reading “Opium”
Despite their limitations, all three approaches to pornography that I have described
provide useful starting points for the analysis of sexual representation, and I want to
consider how they can be applied and developed in relation to one particular example.
My choice of example is the Yves Saint Laurent advert for Opium perfume featuring the
11
PORNOGRAPHY AND OBJECTIFICATION
model Sophie Dahl. This image, though not clearly “pornographic” in terms of its
positioning in the market, became the focus of some controversy and of renewed debate
about pornography and objectification in 2000. The subject of complaint, discussion, and
at least two parodies (the image became the basis of the cover of novelist, Jeanette
Winterson’s The Power Book , and of an advertising campaign for Newcastle Brown Ale the
following year), the Opium advert was described as “the picture that’s divided Britain”
( The Sun 2000, p. 17).
The concerns of all three approaches—regulation, sexual objectification, and aes-
thetics and transgression—were clearly visible in the controversy around the display and
eventual banning of this image from billboards after the Advertising Standards Authority
received over 900 complaints about it. The question of pornography as a regulatory
category received some attention in media coverage which focused on the issue of
acceptable contexts for the display of the advert and on the rights and wrongs of
censorship. Complaints from some members of the public and discussions in the press
suggested some disagreement about whether the advert presented woman as a sexual
object, but the advert was finally condemned by the Advertising Standards Authority as
offensive and degrading to women. Finally, the generic characteristics of the image were
claimed variously as artistic, erotic, and pornographic, and this level of uncertainty about
the generic status of the image is a particularly interesting feature of the Opium
controversy.
Yves Saint Laurent, whose company commissioned the advert, argued that its
image was “a tasteful nude in the tradition of high art” (in The Age 2000). The model, Dahl,
is conventionally beautiful, supine, gleaming, displayed, contorted, and depilated for
maximum visibility, a series of features which are used in the representation of women’s
bodies in the tradition of high art as well as in some forms of mainstream, soft-core
pornography. Indeed, the image was also read in terms of pornographic style. While some
commentators argued that the image was erotic, its power was also commented on as
evidence of a pornographic sensibility. Dyer’s claim that pornography is often identified
by its ability to move the body (Richard Dyer 1992, p.121) may be borne out by these
comments, though this and the use of the term “erotic” as a mark of approval are difficult
to locate in relation to any particular textual elements. More specifically, Dahl’s body may
be read as a “porn body;” her splayed legs, closed eyes and open mouth are characteristic
of soft-core imagery, while her relative fleshiness locates her within pornographic rather
than contemporary fashion codes of beauty, as a signifier of sexual appetite and of the
body’s materiality. In fact, the image appears to draw on codes associated with art,
pornography, and fashion through its combination of high art aesthetics, its display of a
“porn body,” the use of a well-known fashion model, and the evident purpose of the
image as an advert for designer perfume. The term “porn chic” (in Libby Brooks 2000, p.6)
usefully indicates the blurring of codes in the advert.
The different codes which are drawn on in the image and the readings made in
relation to them reveal how pornography is often characterized through a location within
aesthetic hierarchies used to differentiate a body which signifies reason, cleanliness, and
order (Lynda Nead 1992, p.7) from one which is “insistently material, defiantly vulgar,
corporeal” (Kipnis 1996, p.132), and visual pleasures of “contemplation, discrimination
and transcendent value” from those involving “motivation, promiscuity and com-
modification” (Nead 1992, p. 89). However, the blurring of codes in the Opium advert
meant that it was possible to locate it within these hierarchies in different ways. It seems
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin